By Caleb Johnson
I suppose that our evaluation of others is based, not so much on
who they are as themselves, but rather on the face that they present to
the world, and thus it is that often others are surprised when they
learn that I am an anarchist. And I suppose that I can empathize with
the initial confusion, for I myself only gradually came to accept the
label of `anarchist' for many of the same reasons.
Now, I can only imagine what gruesome scenario enters the mind of
each person as he envisions just what, exactly, anarchy might mean for
the world, but I know what it used to mean to me. The mental picture
that I formed of the anarchist was of an angry young man throwing a
homemade bomb. The society he hoped for could only be one of chaos and
disorder, where organized bands of thugs plundered with abandon and
citizens huddled in the darkness of their homes, shivering for fear and
praying for some escape back to civility and civilization. And this
melancholy picture, of course, is as offensive to me as it is to you,
being as I am a peaceful person, more at home sipping tea in a
coffeeshop than I am burning effigies, and more inclined to vacation at a
tropical paradise than to the heart of Somalia.
So, I permit the reader a degree of astonishment at the revelation
that I am an anarchist. It was, in fact, only reluctantly that I
adopted the anarchist label; I learned that many other anarchists have
also eschewed the anarchist label, preferring a more obscure and
therefore less-maligned designation. So why is it that I unabashedly
claim to be an anarchist?
An ancient Jewish scripture makes what I deem to be an accurate
observation, that "one man rules over another to his hurt.” At every
time and at every place throughout history is found the same story:
man's states achieve the subjugation of the masses under the control of
the rich and powerful. War is routine. Tyranny runs rampant. Minorities
are oppressed. Men are conscripted and enslaved. The belongings of the
poor are plundered to pay for greater and greater extravagancies by
those who enjoy the reins of power. The masses starve while a few live
in shameful luxury. Justice is perverted, and people live under
constant threat that their security will be undermined. We tolerate this
depravity for one reason, and one reason only: We are convinced that,
for as bad as the State may be, it is better than the chaos of anarchy.
And it is for this reason that the state must do everything in its power
to demonize anarchy, to equate it with chaos and disorder.
But it seems to me that a great lie has been perpetrated on
mankind. Every war that has ever been fought was created and nurtured by
states. War, that great scourge of mankind, can only exist among
states. When individuals disagree with each other, the argument may
escalate to fisticuffs. Yet, when states squabble, the end result is too
often war, with the millions of deaths and injuries, as well as the
poverty and disease that war entails. And yet the state, the sole author
of the scourge of war, is held on a pedestal. We sing songs to honor
it, make oaths and pledges to it, place its banner in our own places of
worship. We display our loyalty to it with countless banners and
emblems, placed prominently so that all may see our pride. We are not
averse to even permitting our children to be sacrificed in its
interests.
Meanwhile, we deride the anarchist as “reactionary”, but we do not
even comprehend what we mean by such a statement. For it is everywhere
acknowledged that states do evil things. Some men say, as Thomas Braden
famously did in the Saturday Evening Post so many years ago, that they
are glad that the state is immoral. Others say, as did one religious man
with whom I conversed recently, that he prefers not to know everything
that the state does for the ease of his own conscience. And almost
universally, when it comes time to vote people will say things like, “I
voted for the lesser of two evils,” or “I held my nose and voted.” When
polled, only very few claim to be “extremely satisfied” by their rulers,
most claiming to be somewhere between “somewhat satisfied” and
“somewhat dissatisfied” by those who hold office. So whatever else the
situation might be, it cannot be claimed that people view the state as a
paragon of virtue and morality. Yet, the second a person suggests that
we might dispose of the state, he is subjected to ridicule, derision,
even violence. So it seems to me that the true reactionary position is
the one that is averse to considering what alternatives might be
available.
This situation is as puzzling as it is disturbing. It would seem
that every man, seeing as he does that the state is, at best, an
imperfect solution, would incline his ear to see what alternatives
present themselves, hoping that the situation might improve. But this is
not the case. Rather, he satisfies himself that anarchy is
impracticable from the outset, then refuses to entertain any suggestions
to the contrary, his reaction being to put forward any conceivable
obstacle with a sort of desperate finality, as if the fact that there
are obstacles to peace mandates that we continue on in our incredibly
destructive course.
“What,” he asks, “are we to do about murderers? Let them run the
streets?” Now, this is a curious question, because states are themselves
murderers, only they accomplish their killings by the millions rather
than individually. And we not only let them run our streets, as it were,
but we let them patrol them. So it is as if we hire the bank robber to
keep the children from stealing from our raspberry bush; not only that,
we give him the key to our safe. Then we console ourselves that our bank
robber is not as bad as the one that the neighbors hired to safeguard
their raspberry bush.
This situation would be funny if it were not so sad. For it seems
to me that men have been duped. “Listen,” says the would be ruler, “Men
are very evil, and they will try to hurt you, so you need me to protect
you.” But if men are so evil, then how can we trust men to rule over us?
And how can we trust men to follow whatever rules are set up anyway?
Last year, I did not steal, nor did I rape, nor did I plunder or
kill or defraud. Nor would I have done those things even if they had
been legal. I needed no law to inform me of right and wrong; nor, I
trust, did you. On the other hand, how many men did things that they
otherwise would not have done, merely because the state said that it was
okay? Would hundreds of thousands of young men, merely on their own
initiative, have armed themselves to the teeth and journeyed to Iraq to
torture, kill, and terrorize? No, to accomplish that great evil they
needed a state to tell them that it was alright to do what they would
otherwise find repugnant.
I am often told, once I have explained myself, that my position
sounds Utopian. But I wonder if this is not merely the speaker
projecting his own dilemma onto me. For I cannot help but feel that the
state is able to maintain itself only as a result of Utopian thinking.
The anarchist sees crime as inevitable; there are, unfortunately a
few deviants who do not care about harming others, or, worse yet, even
enjoy harming others. So the anarchist accepts this reality. It is a
fact of life. All he can do is try to minimize the risk to himself or to
those he cares about. But the person with Utopian thinking, on the
other hand, is unable to accept this reality. He continues to grasp at
the illusion that crime might be eliminated if only a suitable agency
can be formed. He is oblivious to the fact that any agency powerful
enough to stand up to the strongest evil is also strong enough to become
the strongest evil. It remains only for the criminals to seize control
of this agency. He is also oblivious to the fact that by attempting to
preemptively stop crime he creates the very societal conditions which
allow it to flourish: fear, mistrust, division.
And with what cost does he purchase this increased threat of crime
and violence? The sacrifice of his own liberty. For all of mankind's
experience speaks to the fact that by far the single most common
aggressor against the rights of mankind is, and always will be, states.
In the Declaration of Independence, Thomas Jefferson expressed the
concept that states exist for the purpose of securing our rights. Yet,
what a misguided notion! To see how misguided this notion is, one
merely needs to read the so-called Bill of Rights to the Constitution.
This document attempts to secure for all Americans the rights to freedom
of speech, freedom of worship, freedom of the press, freedom to
peaceably assemble, freedom to bear arms, security against having the
military quartered in my home, security against unreasonable searches
and seizures, and security against unfair judicial proceedings. But who
is it that threatens these rights if it is not states? The argument is,
therefore, circular: I need a state to secure my rights, which rights
are only threatened by states.
Now, before I end this essay, I need to make one thing very clear,
because I think there is a very common misunderstanding of anarchists,
and it a misunderstanding rooted deeply in our very language. In this
essay, I have consistently used the word state. I have tried to avoid
the word “government”. In the minds of many people, these words are
synonymous. And it is for this reason that it is difficult to conceive
of a life without the state.
It is a truism that interaction between men requires a sort of
government. This is evident in all of man's social dealings. A family
exists in some sort of governmental arrangement, inasmuch as there are
roles and understood norms of conduct within each family. Often,
government in this sense is merely informal. In larger groups of people,
it is likely to be more explicit. But what distinguishes these forms of
government from the state is that the state is not voluntary. The state
is really a very specific type of government. It is an authoritarian
model of government that enforces its rule over anyone that it considers
to be within its jurisdiction, regardless of whether or not they have
consented to its rule. In this respect, a state is exactly like the
mafia. In fact, the state differs from the mafia in exactly one respect.
The sole difference between the state and the mafia is that a majority
of the people in any given area acknowledge the legitimacy of the state.
If the majority of people acknowledged the mafia, it would be called
“the government”. That is the sole difference between the two
organizations. And the reader would do well to reflect on that. Because
it is a universally acknowledged principle that the minority are
entitled to the same considerations as the majority. But how can this be
if the majority reserve the right to impose, at the most fundamental
level, a form of governance upon the minority that is opposed to his
conscience?
It is sad that all of mankind's “national governments” are states.
What an anarchist objects to is being forced to adhere to an
organization to which he has not given his consent, from which he may
not withdraw if it violates his conscience, and which provides its
“services” in a coercive rather than a voluntary way. At the heart of
the anarchist argument is a desire to uphold peace and morality, freedom
and brotherhood. An anarchist acknowledges a simple truth: that any
relationship that is not consensual can only result in further violence;
but that a relationship among a group of people that recognizes the
value of each individual, that acknowledges his ultimate ability to
choose whether to continue that relationship, is based on the greatest
bonds of fraternity. This, and not bomb-throwing, is the legacy of
anarchism.
No comments:
Post a Comment